Historical fiction at the service of Lockean liberalism

It is unfortunate that C. Bradley Thompson’s America’s Revolutionary Mind has been marketed as a genuine American history, rather than the libertarian fan-fiction that it is.

Historical fiction is an honorable literary genre and there is no shame in writing it. Unfortunately, America’s Revolutionary Mind by C. Bradley Thompson has been marketed as a genuine American history, rather than the libertarian fan-fiction that it is.

Thompson, a professor of political philosophy at Clemson University, could have written a good, or at least tolerable, history, but his ambition and ideology overtook his scholarship. Since his book was published last year, he has worked to keep it in the public eye, promoting his thesis that the “American Revolution and the Declaration that expressed it were the existential embodiment of the Enlightenment’s highest ideals.” Specifically, he argues that “America’s revolutionary mind is virtually synonymous with John Locke’s mind.” And, since Thompson sees the Constitution as a fulfillment of the Declaration, this means that the full Founding era is to be understood through Locke.

As is typical of historical fiction, there is some truth in this, but Thompson exaggerates and distorts Locke’s influence in order to construct an ideal libertarian version of the American Founding. That Locke’s thought influenced the colonial leaders of independence whom we now call the Founders, especially Jefferson, is not in dispute. One need only look at the famous opening passages of the Declaration of Independence, which Thompson does, interminably. But many other elements were also in play, with the Founders often engaging in a sort of political syncretism. A variety of sources—including Christianity (mostly Reformed), the English common law heritage, a long tradition of colonial self-government and an admiration for classical republicanism—informed colonial resistance to British rule and the subsequent establishment of the United States of America.

Thompson could have explored the role of Locke’s ideas amidst this multiplicity of influences. Instead, he reduced the complex history of American independence to a single philosophical narrative, defined by the Declaration, which in turn he defines as Lockean liberalism. For Thompson, the trick is to ignore or minimize other intellectual currents that shaped American independence and the Founding. In cases where this disregard is impossible, he seeks to absorb non-Lockean factors into his narrow narrative. This one-sided history obscures as much as it illuminates, and Thompson’s methodological sleights-of-hand are apparent long before the reader finishes slogging through the nearly 400 pages of text.

Consequently, Thompson gives his readers an inaccurate impression of American religion during the Founding era. He quotes sermons that include Lockean reasoning, but he passes over a multitude of examples that would complicate his narrative, such as praise for God’s providential guidance of the American cause and calls for the people to repent of their sins lest God withdraw his favor. As can be seen in Ellis Sandoz’s excellent collection of political sermons from the time, these themes of sin and providence were common. Most Americans were not Jeffersonian deists. Rather, they believed in an intervening, judging God who expected collective righteousness from His people in America. But Thompson seems uncomfortable with this reality and eager to write religion out of his account of American life. He does not discuss Reformed covenant theology and practice as an influence on American ideas of social contracts. And, perhaps most egregiously, Thompson excises Christianity from his discussion of the abolitionist movement, reducing it to Declaration-inspired libertarianism.

Likewise, Thompson downplays the influence and inspiration of classical republicanism on American leaders. References to antiquity abounded during the Founding period. The moral outlook of the Founders was Christian and classical, not Lockean, but Thompson ignores the Christian influences and only acknowledges the classical ones in passing. Colonial writers regularly adopted Latin pen names, most famously in the case of the authors of the Federalist Papers—which are full of references to Greek and Roman history, and almost devoid of Locke, who is not even mentioned by name, though other modern thinkers like Montesquieu are. This enthusiasm for antiquity spilled over into our government: we have a Senate not because it is demanded by Lockean political theory, but because Rome had one.

Thompson treats factors that he cannot ignore—such as the Americans’ common-law heritage, commitment to the rights of Englishmen and history of self-government—as merely preparatory for a Lockean consummation in the Declaration of Independence. In his telling, though the Americans may have begun by defending their ancient rights and liberties from British imperial encroachment, they became full-fledged Enlightenment liberals under the tutelage of Locke’s ideas, which they increasingly turned to as the confrontation with England escalated.

The Declaration itself is Thompson’s primary evidence for this revisionist thesis. He argues that the Declaration “brought together ideas and assumptions that had hitherto been incomplete, unclear, or discordant” and he therefore describes the Declaration as an “ideological road map” from which he is able to construct a “near-unified system of thought” that defines “America’s revolutionary mind.” Still, although he engages in extended exegesis of the document, he neglects its actual composition, the details of which undermine his case. Jefferson did not write it as a carefully-crafted philosophical treatise, but cranked it out on deadline, borrowing heavily from George Mason’s work while probably having a few drinks. Thus, interpreters should not overlook the possibility that, in some passages, Jefferson just winged it and wrote something that sounded good. Thompson is horrified at the thought, but there is indeed some “manipulative propaganda” in the Declaration.

Furthermore, had John Adams not handed the Declaration’s drafting off to Jefferson, the Americans would have still declared and fought for independence without the Lockean rhetoric Jefferson included. The purpose of the Declaration was not, as Thompson asserts, to “declare certain self-evident truths.” Rather, it was to declare independence. And though Thompson sometimes treats the Declaration itself as the cause of conflict with Great Britain, writing that its signers “heroically assumed full responsibility for the war that was sure to come,” he knows that it was not drafted until over a year after the war had begun.

Thus, a Lockean exegesis of the Declaration is insufficient to prove Thompson’s case. Perhaps sensing this, he undertakes extensive efforts to demonstrate that Locke’s political philosophy was the dominant mode of patriot thought. But aside from Jefferson and a few minor figures such as Ethan Allen (whom Thompson attempts to elevate as “one of America’s leading thinkers”), there is not much evidence that the Founders were “unadulterated Lockeans.” Thompson presents scant evidence that the likes of Washington, Madison, Franklin and Hamilton were committed to Locke’s philosophy. He does make a case that John Adams was impressed by Locke as a young man, but he has little evidence that Locke dominated Adams’ later thinking. Indeed, Thompson is reduced to purporting to discern a “disguised Lockeanism veiled in the more traditional language of English constitutional jurisprudence” in the revolutionary-era Adams.

It is true that Locke’s ideas were part of the intellectual mix of the time, and the references add up—here a sermon, here a pamphlet, here a newspaper article, here a speech—but what they add up to is less than Lockean hegemony during the Founding era. Thus, Thompson attempts to bolster his case by presuming that statements that sound Lockean were inspired by his philosophy and by treating favorable reference to Locke as an endorsement of his whole philosophy. Thus, he describes a group of “hardscrabble yeoman farmers” as “Lockean purists” even though they had likely never heard of Locke.

Perhaps, in Thompson’s mind, the principle of hermeneutic charity means reading everyone and everything in as Lockean a way as possible. But not even those who cited Locke as an authority necessarily understood his philosophy. Then as now, many Americans made a habit of referencing figures they little understood.

Additionally, not everyone who used phrases similar to Locke’s meant the same thing he did; there were many sources besides Locke for ideas about the rights of man, the nature of happiness, and the laws of nature and nature’s God. Most were more traditional than Locke, but a few were more radical. For instance, Thomas Paine’s Common Sense was more widely read and immediately influential than Locke’s work. But Thompson seems uncomfortable with Paine’s radicalism, as most Americans also came to be, especially when its implications became clear as the French Revolution devolved into terror and borderline genocide.

Perhaps Thompson views Locke’s philosophy as providing a golden mean between radicals such as Paine and the more conservative American patriots who saw themselves as defending their traditional rights, liberties and practices of self-government. But a golden mean is not the same as a dominant influence. Regardless, Thompson’s ideological reach exceeds his historical grasp. This is why the esteemed historian Gordon Wood, who has spent a career exploring the complexities of the Founding, provided the most diffident of back-cover blurbs, writing that Thompson’s book is a “bold new interpretation of the political and moral theory of the American Revolution. It is sure to be provocative.” Well, yes.

The provocation is not just the historical inaccuracy. Thompson’s project is history in service to ideology, and he exhorts his readers to embrace the libertarian or classical liberal ideals that he argues the nation was established upon. While Thompson’s ideology is less dangerous that others, it is still unsound. If the United States of America was founded on Lockean ideas, it was built on a philosophical foundation of sand whose collapse will likely lead to something worse.

The dangers may be seen in Thompson’s assertion that in the long-term, the Revolution’s effect “was to liberate men from unchosen obligations to each other.” Fortunately, this Luciferian independence and pride was far from typical of the Founders, who were neither moral libertarians nor believers in “radical individualism.” Moralistic legislation in the early United States was accepted and even expected; Americans did not believe in guaranteeing “to each and every person the freedom and the right to pursue happiness as he defines and seeks it.” Rather, they believed not only that the pursuit of happiness required virtue, but that government had a duty as a moral instructor and a restraint on evil, sometimes including prohibitions on private wickedness.

It must also be noted that Thompson’s Lockean liberal or libertarian ideology is not benignly neglectful of potential rivals. Liberalism is not neutral with regard to competing conceptions of the good. Thus, when Thompson concludes with an a epilogue that is indebted to the late Claremont scholar Harry Jaffa, it is a warning, as an examination of Jaffa’s work reveals that his liberal theory endorses the violent suppression and disenfranchisement of non-liberals. Political liberalism cannot keep its promise of neutrality between different worldviews. Locke, at least, was honest about the limits of toleration within his system (Catholics, for instance, were not included) in a way that his current apologists like Thompson are not.

Fortunately, America was not founded as a nation dedicated to Lockean ideology. We may enjoy the benefits of our liberal practices, such as the right to trial by jury, knowing that they have deeper roots than the shallow soil of liberal theory.

America’s Revolutionary Mind: A Moral History of the American Revolution and the Declaration That Defined It
By C. Bradley Thompson
Encounter Books, 2019
Hardcover, 584 pages

Related at CWR: America on Trial: A Catholic World Report Symposium” (July 3, 2020)


If you value the news and views Catholic World Report provides, please consider donating to support our efforts. Your contribution will help us continue to make CWR available to all readers worldwide for free, without a subscription. Thank you for your generosity!

Click here for more information on donating to CWR. Click here to sign up for our newsletter.


About Nathanael Blake 21 Articles
Nathanael Blake, PhD, is a Postdoctoral Fellow at the Ethics and Public Policy Center. His primary research interests are American political theory, Christian political thought, and the intersection of natural law and philosophical hermeneutics. His published scholarship has focused on Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Hans-Georg Gadamer, Alasdair MacIntyre and Russell Kirk. He is currently working on a study of J.R.R. Tolkien’s anti-rationalism. He writes from Virginia.

8 Comments

  1. A brilliant article!

    In one of your linked articles the author writes: “Neutrality may sometimes be a useful legal fiction, but it is a practical impossibility. Thus, while French, as an accomplished lawyer, outclassed Ahmari regarding legal questions during their dispute, he has in turn struggled to address the philosophical issues raised by liberalism’s obvious practical partiality. Liberal ideology is not neutral between competing conceptions of the highest good and the ultimate end of human beings. As Jaffa understood, even if French does not, liberal doctrines necessarily require disenfranchising and punishing those who hold rival beliefs. Liberal ideology is jealous, and will have no other gods before it.”

    I would add that there is and can be no such thing as neutrality between competing conceptions of the highest good and the ultimate end of human beings. Judaeo-Christianity has the correct one, with the consequences Jaffa correctly identifies.

  2. In his excellent review, Blake also writes: “Jefferson did not write it [the Declaration of Independence] as a carefully-crafted philosophical treatise, but cranked it out on deadline, borrowing heavily from George Mason’s work while probably having a few drinks. Thus, interpreters should not overlook the possibility that, in some passages, Jefferson just winged it and wrote something that sounded good.”

    OR, limiting the possibility of even sometimes winging it, maybe Jefferson in his breadth consistently drew from an exceptional memory?

    Sylvester J. McNamara documents the thesis that one of the many sources other than Locke (Blake’s critique) that Jefferson turned to was Bellarmine. Some of the at-least circumstantial evidence includes Jefferson’s copy of Filmer’s “Patriarcha” (now in the Library of Congress), plus McNamara’s side-by-side display of the “extraordinary identity of the principles existing between it [Bellarmine in the first dozen pages of the ‘Patriarcha’] and the [Jefferson’s] Virginian and American preambles [which] is accounted for by the fact, narrated by Jefferson’s biographers, that he had a most TENACIOUS MEMORY and was gifted with a wonderful faculty of expressing thoughts digested” (“American Democracy and Catholic Doctrine,” Brooklyn: International Catholic Truth Society, c. 1919-1933).

    Then, (again consistent with Blake’s critique) in the American preamble to the Declaration the more rationalistic or Enlightenment term “self-evident” (truths) was an EDIT supplied by Benjamin Franklin, replacing Jefferson’s original and more deeply grounded “sacred and undeniable” (Paul Johnson, “A History of the American People,” 1999).

  3. Something strange has happened to conservative professors. It used to be that liberal professors would cherry pick all their evidence to construct a false narrative. They would use all the usual tricks of truncating quotes, taking things out of context, imputing evil motives where there were none, etc. Now conservative professors are doing the same thing, usually to promote some weird libertarianism. The only real scholarship is honest and evaluates all evidence carefully, neither exaggerating nor giving undue emphasis to obscure things. But suddenly, with Deneen, that dude that blocks everyone from harvard (Vermule?) and now this guy, they all lie and distort as much as liberal professors. It’s a sad day when that happens. All they do is waste everyone’s time putting forth false narratives that are eventually discredited because the obvious flaws are obvious.

  4. Does created equal really need such extended exegesis, ringing out promissory notes against slavery and abortion sounds pretty good.

  5. Very interesting article. History sure is complicated. When a layman or should I say lay person reads history one needs to be aware of the author biases. It is easy to take in the presentation of an author who has great creditials and take the thesis in as fact. As someone who likes books on the American founding, the Founding Fathers, etc, I thought Thompson’s book would be a useful book to read, now not so much. However this article by itself was very informative. It concisely covers essentials points on America’s founding worth restoring in my aging memory bank.

5 Trackbacks / Pingbacks

  1. Historical fiction at the service of Lockean liberalism | Catholic Canada
  2. Liberalism as Christian Personalism? – Nathanel Blake – Instituto Acton
  3. Conservatism Doesn't Mean Putting Whorehouses In Boys' Pockets ⋆ 10z Viral
  4. Conservatives Must Understand Where They Went Wrong Before They Can Go Right - Western Legends Research
  5. Conservatives Must Understand Where They Went Wrong Before They Can Go Right - Barbershop Talk

Leave a Reply to SOL Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published.

All comments posted at Catholic World Report are moderated. While vigorous debate is welcome and encouraged, please note that in the interest of maintaining a civilized and helpful level of discussion, comments containing obscene language or personal attacks—or those that are deemed by the editors to be needlessly combative or inflammatory—will not be published. Thank you.


*