Is opposition to the death penalty Thomistic?

Given Pope Francis’s own high regard for St. Thomas (together with the historical papal approbation he has enjoyed) when it comes to doctrinal issues, we might ask how the opposition to the death penalty articulated by the Pope compares with the teaching of the Doctor Communis.

Detail from "Apotheosis of St. Thomas Aquinas" (1631) by Francisco de Zurbaran [WikiArt.org]

In an apparent effort to reassure his audience of the orthodoxy of Amoris laetitia, speaking at the opening of a diocesan conference in Rome in June 2016, Pope Francis appealed to St. Thomas Aquinas. “So that you might be at peace,” he said, “I must tell you that what is written in the Exhortation … from beginning to end, is entirely Thomistic. It is sound doctrine (dottrina sicura).” The Pope told his audience that in making this claim, he was reaffirming something already asserted by Cardinal Christoph Schönborn of Vienna, “a great theologian who was secretary of the Congregation for the Doctrine of the faith” – not to mention a member of St. Thomas’s own Dominican order.

The Holy Father has repeated his characterization of Amoris laetitia as Thomistic on a couple of occasions. Speaking to the Jesuits assembled in Rome in October 2016 for their 36th general congregation, Pope Francis told them that “the morality of Amoris laetitia is Thomistic.” And again speaking to Jesuits, but this time in Colombia in September, the Pope had this to say:

Some people contend that the morality that is at the foundation of Amoris laetitia isn’t a Catholic morality, or at least that it isn’t sound morality (moral segura). In response, I would like clearly to reaffirm that the morality of Amoris laetitia is Thomistic; it is that of the great Thomas.

However, not everyone agrees with Pope Francis about the Thomistic nature of Amoris laetitia. It is disputed, for instance, by some of Cardinal Schönborn’s Dominican confreres. Here I have in mind Basil Cole (here and here) and Thomas Crean (here).

While I must admit that my sympathies lie with Cole and Crean, I don’t want in this essay to enter into the debate about the alleged Thomistic nature of Amoris laetitia. My purpose in mentioning the Pope’s claims about the document is only to highlight the privileged place that he has repeatedly assigned to St. Thomas as a standard in judgments about doctrinal matters. These gestures of Papa Bergoglio are not, as we know, anomalous in the history of the Holy See. Since John XXII, who canonized Thomas in 1323, pope after pope has commended Thomas’s doctrinal guidance. This statement by Urban V to the archbishop of Toulouse and to the professors of its university in 1368 is typical:

Moreover, we wish, and it is the purpose of the present letter, to enjoin upon you that you adhere to the teaching of the said Blessed Thomas as the true and Catholic teaching, and that you endeavor to spread it with all your power.i

Signaling his agreement with previous papal directives, in 1777 Pius VI wrote:

In many schools Thomas Aquinas was rightly called the Sun of doctrine (Sol doctrinae) and the standard for theologians, because he taught only what was consistent with Sacred Scripture and the Fathers … And so our predecessors commended his doctrine with outstanding praises as the shield of Christian religion and the resolute guardian of the Church.ii

Of course, we could go on. The esteem that later pontiffs had for St. Thomas – Leo XIII, for example – is common knowledge. The point – easily made – is that Pope Francis’s appeal to the doctrinal authority of St. Thomas has excellent papal precedent.

Pope Francis’s recent remarks on the death penalty

By now, anyone who follows Catholic Church news is aware that Pope Francis has recently made some surprising statements in opposition to the death penalty. Speaking on October 11 to a gathering organized by the Pontifical Council for the Promotion of the New Evangelization, the Pope proposed what he understood to be a legitimate development of the Church’s teaching on the death penalty. The Pope’s remarks strongly suggest that he regards recourse to the death penalty as never morally acceptable:

It must be forcefully affirmed that it is inhuman to condemn a person to death and that, however the sentence is carried out, it humiliates personal dignity. In itself it is contrary to the Gospel because it is a free decision to suppress a human life that is always sacred in the eyes of the Creator and that, in the final analysis, has God alone as the true judge and guarantor.

But how does the Holy Father explain the Church’s previous acceptance of the death penalty as a legitimate measure taken by the state? On the one hand, he believes that historical circumstances and a certain social immaturity prevented us from seeing clearly.

In past centuries, when there were few means of defense and social maturity had not yet enjoyed a positive development, recourse to the death penalty appeared to be a logical consequence of the application of the justice that needed to be respected.

On the other hand, he believes that because she was too much concerned with material power and wealth, the Church over-valued law and was blind to what the Gospel really demanded.

The preoccupation with protecting material power and wealth led to an exaggerated regard for the value of law and prevented a deeper understanding of the Gospel.

Edward Feser (here, here, and here), Brian Harrison (here), Eduardo Echeverria (here), and others have questioned the soundness of the Pope’s recent statements about the death penalty. I think they raise very important points, points that merit our (and the Holy Father’s) consideration.

St. Thomas, law, punishment, and the death penalty

Given Pope Francis’s own high regard for St. Thomas (together with the historical papal approbation he has enjoyed) when it comes to doctrinal issues, we might ask how the opposition to the death penalty articulated by the Pope compares with the teaching of the Doctor Communis.

In his treatise on law in the Summa theologiae,iii Thomas explains that the laws of a political community and the punishments for violating them must be consistent with the natural law and that they have the purpose of leading people to virtue. To be sure, he doesn’t believe that they are sufficient for that purpose. They are just one piece of the puzzle, an important piece indeed, but just one piece nonetheless. The laws and punishments instituted by a political community supplement the moral formation provided by families and the Church.

Thomas also holds that laws and punishments must be appropriate to the general character of the political community in which they have been instituted. He is, thus, prepared to accept a great deal of diversity in laws and punishments across political communities and across time. This too he makes clear in the Summa’s treatise on law.iv

The end of the virtuous life that we live in the present, says Thomas, is “heavenly beatitude (beatitudo caelestis).”v He sees this as the ultimate reason why virtue should be promoted in political communities. It is, therefore, the ultimate purpose of all laws and punishments. Thomas conceives of the Church and the temporal power as formally distinct from each other but also sees the latter as being subordinately ordered to the proper ends of the former. Thomas, you see, isn’t terribly modern.

Because he thinks that laws and punishments must be appropriate to the people to whom they apply and knows that this will entail differences across political communities, Thomas is no absolutist about the implementation of the death penalty. In Summa contra gentiles, III, 146, Thomas says, for example, that “the execution of wicked people (malorum) is forbidden wherever it cannot be done without danger to good people (bonorum).” We have every reason to believe, then, that he would recognize the legitimacy of a prudential opposition to the death penalty of the sort that John Paul II has called for, which is not to say that he would necessarily agree with John Paul II’s particular reasoning.

But Thomas would not accept the claim that the death penalty is, in principle, morally impermissible, that is, that the death penalty is what moralists call a malum in se (“evil in itself”). Put otherwise, Thomas would not accept a principled opposition (as opposed to a prudential one) to the death penalty. In Thomas’s view, the death penalty is a morally acceptable means of punishment. On this he takes himself to be following the teaching of Scripture. Consider this string of quotes he offers to support his position in Summa contra gentiles, III, 46:

The Apostle says, therefore, in 1 Corinthians 5:6: “Know you not that a little leaven corrupts the whole lump?” And a little later he adds: “Put away the evil one from among yourselves.” And in Romans 13:4 it is said of earthly power that “he does not carry the sword in vain: for he is God’s minister, an avenger to execute wrath upon him who does evil.” And in 1 Peter 2:13-14 it is said: “Be subject therefore to every human creature for God’s sake: whether it be to the king as excelling, or to governors as sent by him for the punishment of evildoers and for the praise of the good.”

Thomas might have added other passages from Scripture. For instance, Genesis 9:6 and John 19:11.

However counterintuitive it may appear to us at first glance, Thomas regards the death penalty – like all other punishments (if properly implemented) – as an aid to virtue and, ultimately, to heavenly beatitude. This it does by functioning, he believes, as a deterrentvi and by protecting the political community from people who are a threat to the peaceful order that is conducive to virtue.vii Furthermore, in his impending execution, Thomas thinks that a person condemned to death has a powerful stimulus to conversion.viii In that respect, you could argue that Thomas understands the death penalty also as rehabilitative.ix

Commenting on this last point, Thomas has a response to the proposal of life imprisonment as an alternative to the death penalty:

The fact that wicked people, as long as they live, can be corrected from their errors does not prohibit the fact that they may be justly executed, for the danger which threatens from their way of life is greater and more certain than the good which may be expected from their improvement. They also have at the critical point of death the opportunity to be converted to God through repentance. And if they are so stubborn that even at the point of death their heart does not draw back from evil, it is possible to make a highly probable judgment that they would never come away from evil to the right use of their powers.x

I don’t think that this is a decisive argument against life imprisonment as an alternative to the death penalty. Even so, Thomas’s reasoning is worth considering.

But Thomas might reject life imprisonment as an alternative to the death penalty for other reasons. Thomas thinks that the death penalty can likewise serve “natural equity” (naturalis aequitatis). Here’s how he puts it:

Natural equity seems to demand that each person be deprived of the good against which he acts, for by this action he renders himself unworthy of such a good. So it is that, according to civil justice, he who offends against the political community is deprived completely of association with it, either by death or by perpetual exile.xi

The particular example that Thomas uses here in discussing recourse to the death penalty (offense against the political community) isn’t important. What is important is his suggestion that natural equity itself might require the life of the criminal. In other words, even if life imprisonment were an option, it might not always be the just option, or so Thomas would appear to think. Whether in a particular case it would be the just option would, presumably, depend on the right prudential judgment of the relevant public authority.

Some people might wonder whether Thomas’s endorsement of the legitimacy of the death penalty is consistent with what he says about human dignity. As the work of Lawrence Dewan, Elinor Gardner, and others makes clear, this isn’t an issue that Thomas overlooks.xii He addresses it directly in Summa theologiae, IIa-IIae, q. 64, a. 2. There is a certain dignity that we always retain as human persons, namely, the dignity of our nature. No evil deed we do nor any evil we suffer can eliminate that dignity. Thomas implies this in the body of q. 64, a. 6. It isn’t because human persons are human that we are punished, whether by the death penalty or any other punishment. We are punished for our actions, actions that aren’t in accord with the dignity of our nature. If we only ever considered each person’s human nature in the abstract and not his concrete actions, it would seem that we could never have grounds for punishing anyone in any way. In q. 64, a. 2, ad 3, Thomas says that by sinning a person falls away from his human dignity (decidit a dignitate humana). Thomas can’t mean by this that by sinning we absolutely lose the human dignity that belongs to us by nature. He must mean either that we have lost some acquired, i.e., non-natural, human dignity or simply that our actions aren’t what they should be given our nature. Whatever the truth of the matter, the punishment for our sins – including the death penalty – that Thomas goes on to discuss in ad 3 is meted out not because of our nature but because of the evil that we have done.

The Pope and St. Thomas

I don’t pretend to give a complete treatment of Thomas’s teaching on the death penalty in the foregoing, only to present what is sufficient for my purposes here. I should also add that, although I agree with a lot of Thomas’s teaching on this matter, I’m not trying to defend that teaching in this essay. My aim is expository.

It’s important to notice that none of the motivations that Pope Francis attributes to previous Catholic proponents of the death penalty can be attributed to Thomas in any obvious way. Does Thomas propose the death penalty because the political community of his time had few other means of defense? That consideration doesn’t explicitly enter into his reasoning. The burden of proof, therefore, would be on people who want to claim it as determinative of his thought. As we have seen, if life imprisonment were suggested to him as an alternative to the death penalty, it’s not evident that he would see it as a wise or even just alternative.

Does Thomas lack social maturity (maturità sociale)? It’s not clear to me what the Holy Father intends by this locution. He doesn’t explain it and its meaning isn’t self-evident. Because of that, we can’t reasonably make any judgments about Thomas on this score.

Does Thomas’s concern for law stem from a preoccupation with protecting material wealth and power? Hardly. As we have seen, for Thomas, law is above all in the service of virtue and heavenly beatitude.

Does a preoccupation with protecting material wealth and power prevent Thomas from achieving a deeper understanding of the Gospel’s teaching on human dignity? Well, what can I say? Thomas doesn’t strike me as someone obsessed with material wealth and power. Moreover, these things don’t figure in any significant way in his teaching on the death penalty. He holds that our nature confers a dignity upon each one of us, but he doesn’t regard human dignity as constituting the only relevant consideration when it comes to punishment or the death penalty. Our actions must also be evaluated.

As I observed at the beginning of this essay, Pope Francis (like so many of his predecessors) has a high regard for Thomas’s judgment in doctrinal matters. One way that he has defended the soundness of the teaching of Amoris laetitia is simply to claim that it is Thomistic. But the Pope’s views on the death penalty seem to be profoundly at odds with Thomas’s. It may be, however, that the Holy Father has failed to express himself properly or that I have just misunderstood him. Regardless of whether either of these is true, I’m sure the Holy Father would agree that he could only benefit from a careful review of what Thomas has to say about the death penalty and from reflection on the extent to which his personal views may depart from Thomas if they do at all.

Endnotes:

i Laudabilis Deus in J.J. Berthier (ed.), Sanctus Thomas Aquinas: Doctor Communis Ecclesiae, vol. I, Testimonia Ecclesiae (Rome: Editrice Nazionale, 1914), 64.

ii Speech to the general chapter of the Dominican order in Rome, May 17, 1777 in B.M. Reichert (ed.), Monumenta Ordinis Fratrum Praedicatorum Historica, vol. XIV, Acta Capitolarum Generalium, vol. IX (Rome: Propaganda Fide, 1904), 310.

iii Ia-IIae, qq. 90-108

iv Especially in qq. 94-97.

v De regno, 16.

vi Summa theologiae, Ia-IIae, q. 87, a. 3, ad 2.

vii Summa contra gentiles, III, 146; Summa theologiae, IIa-IIae, q. 108, a. 3, ad 2; De regno, 16.

viii Summa contra gentiles, III, 146.

ix Ed Feser and Joseph Bessette offer the same interpretation. See their By Man Shall His Blood Be Shed: A Catholic Defense of the Death Penalty (San Francisco: Ignatius Press), 199.

x Summa contra gentiles, III, 146.

xi Summa contra gentiles, III, 144.

xii Lawrence Dewan, “Thomas Aquinas, Gerard Bradley, and the Death Penalty: Some Observations.” Gregorianum 82 (2001): 152-161; Elinor Gardner, Saint Thomas Aquinas on the Death Penalty. PhD dissertation, Boston College, 2009, 288-303. Gardner’s dissertation is available online here. Dewan’s and Gardner’s discussions of this issue are detailed and nuanced and I highly recommend them, especially because I don’t have the space here to be as detailed or nuanced.


If you value the news and views Catholic World Report provides, please consider donating to support our efforts. Your contribution will help us continue to make CWR available to all readers worldwide for free, without a subscription. Thank you for your generosity!

Click here for more information on donating to CWR. Click here to sign up for our newsletter.


About Joseph G. Trabbic 15 Articles
Joseph G. Trabbic is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Ave Maria University. He has published in various academic journals, including Religious Studies, International Journal of Philosophy and Theology, and New Blackfriars. He is also a contributor to Thomistica.net.

17 Comments

  1. Intrinsically evil.

    How is the New Catechism of the Catholic Church going to word this without admitting error. Nonsense about being confused or “clouded” ; “clear”, now, because enough time has passed and we are “modern”?

    How does this pope not understand what such a declaration means in that every instance of capital punishment carried out – past, present and future – has been, is, and will be gravely immoral and absolutely wrong.

    There is simply no way to square this circle…the Church did not have this new “infallible” truth then on a monumental moral issue.

    Error.

  2. Ivereigh’s “Team13” is counterfeit, and insists on “ruling” on the basis of the personal “charms” of “the current pontiff.”

    It is determined to get away with anything and everything – but since it so obviously contradicts 2000 years of Church teaching before 2013, the flick do not recognize the voice of “Team13” and PF, so now “Team13” and PF are trying to “reinvent” Aquinas and JP2 and every other faithful authority in order to convince the flock that the voice they hear is not counterfeit.

    Pathetic.

    May the Holy Spirit overcome them in all things, until they recant or resign or are replaced.

  3. A sterling article! The law of God as originally given to Adam and broken by Cain was that the direct and voluntary killing of a human being without authorisation of divine law is always and intrinsically gravely immoral.

    For the Church’s traditional doctrine on the death penalty to be at all defensible, the divine law enabling the use of capital punishment must have been promulgated and must therefore be at least de fide divina.

    The formula of the definitive teaching of Pope St John Paul II in Evangelium Vitae is that the direct and voluntary killing of an innocent human being is always gravely immoral. It is de fide divine et catholica.

    The elements of the teaching are: ‘direct and voluntary’, ‘killing’, ‘innocent’ and ‘human being’. Each is necessary to the inerrancy of the teaching.

    Thus, the attempt by Pope Francis to remove the word ‘innocent’ from the teaching amounts to a sin of heresy.

  4. Joseph,
    Stay in the mix. Nice essay. I’m departing the Catholic internet because it is a drug that helps us escape cleaning behind the refrigerator. And no Catholic, either liberal or conservative, is arguing on behalf of murder victims which is a scandal that will break on the Church in a hundred years from now…but we keep sending God scandals of the right or of the left side of theology. The Church, while anti death penalty, will get tens of thousands of murder victims killed which is a figure e.g….just for Brazil…61,600 murdered in 2016 with no death penalty while China, also poverty laden if using normal measures, has 11,000 murder victims yearly with 7 times the population of Brazil. SCOTUS declared the death penalty saves lives in 1976 after four years of research and our Popes circumvented that hard work by inverting deterrence to mean….deterring the “aggressor” you caught only….in ccc 2267. Joseph….check SCOTUS’s 1976 decision and check world homicide rates by UN stats.
    Dominant mild affluence stops murders ( Europe) where poor people are few or non rebellious….the death penalty stops murders wherever the poor number in the millions ( Asia) . Brazil to Mexico is non death penalty and is the most murderous region on earth by UN murder rates and is heavily nominally Catholic. Asia is the safest area on earth…with millions of poor…and is death penalty dominant. The catechism in ccc 2267 is euro centric….and I’m being
    nice. Your opposition Catholics slither around every Bible verse like eels on a boat deck. Good luck with that. It’s about saving lives amongst the poor by deterrence….something no modern post Paul VI Pope researched.

    • I commend Prof. Trabbic for his thoughtful article. He is correct that many popes, including Pope Francis, have praised St. Thomas Aquinas. It should be noted, however, that the popes—while extolling the scholastic method of St. Thomas—never felt bound to uphold all of his positions. St. Thomas, for example, maintained that “the Blessed Virgin did indeed contract original sin” (ST III, q. 27, art. 2, ad. 2), but Bl. Pius IX dogmatically rejected this position is his 1854 solemn definition of the Immaculate Conception (D-H, 2803). St. Thomas did not believe that episcopal ordination brought about a sacramental order (ST Suppl. q. 40 a. 5 ad 2), but Pius XII determined otherwise in 1947 (D-H, 3859) as well as Vatican II in 1964 (LG, 21; D-H, 4145). As is well-know, St. Thomas upheld delayed hominization (cf. Summa contra Gentiles II, 87–89 and De Potentia III, q. 9 ad 9). The Church today, however, believes that human life ‘must be recognized as having the rights of a person” from “the moment of conception” (CCC, 2270).

      Some have tried to use Thomistic principles to defend the full personhood of human life from the moment of conception, and I suppose something similar could be done with St. Thomas’ teachings about capital punishment. For example, in ST II-II, q. 64, a. 2, the Angelic Doctor argues that a man who is “dangerous or infectious to the community” might need to be killed for the sake of “the common good.” If, though, non-lethal means would suffice in removing such a dangerous man from the community, there would be no need to execute him. With regard to retribution for heinous crimes, St. Thomas states in ST II-II, q. 66, a. 6 ad 1 that “punishments in this life are medicinal rather than retributive, for retribution is reserved to divine judgment.” This might argue against execution as a means for retribution in this life. The arguments, I suppose, could go back and forth as to whether the current papal rejection of the death penalty could be harmonized with the words of St. Thomas.

      There is, though, another aspect of St. Thomas’ thought that would argue in favor of Pope Francis’ view on the death penalty. This is found in St. Thomas’ recognition that “the teaching itself of Catholic Doctors has its authority from the Church (et ipsa doctrina Catholicorum doctorum ab Ecclesia auctoritatem habet; ST II-II q. 10 a. 12). This means that the teachings of Catholic Doctors, including St. Thomas, must be judged in light of magisterial teaching and not vice versa. The words of the Angelic Doctor are quite clear on this matter, for he says: “The authority of the Church must be observed rather than the authority of Augustine or Jerome or any Doctor whatsoever” (magis standum est auctoritati Ecclesiae quam auctoritati vel Augustini vel Hieronymi vel cuiuscumque doctoris; ST II-II q. 10 a. 12). Since Pope Francis, with papal authority, teaches that “the Church firmly rejects the death penalty” (Amoris laetitia, 83), Catholics, following the mind of St. Thomas, should also “firmly reject the death penalty.” This follows from the very words of Aquinas himself who recognized that the teaching of any Doctor of the Church must yield to the authority of the Church. Such authority, for St. Thomas, is found in the bishops and the pope who hold the “magisterium cathedrae pastoralis” (cf. In IV Sent. 19,2,2, q. 3 sol. 2 ad 4).

      • Your position (here and in your articles) has a strange quirk that it places enormous Magisterial weight on contradictions, while repeating the traditional teaching has little or no Magisterial weight whatsoever.

        Any number of Popes and Councils can address this issue, and their consistency, and the matter and content of their interventions are of absolutely no account in your reckoning. It is precisely because Pope Francis’s comments run against this tradition that you give them so much heft, that, and of course because they are the most recent…

        That is, doctrine works as a kind of switch which can only be thrown once. All of the previous Popes and Councils reaffirmed the teaching as it had always been, so the switch stayed in its original position.

        Strangely, if Pope Francis had just echoed what the Church had always taught, contentedly quoting Pope Pius XII, for example, the “switch” still wouldn’t have been thrown, and presumably what he taught would count just as little as what all of them taught, just waiting to be overthrown.

        But he broke ranks, as it were, taught something novel and contradictory, and so the switch got thrown, and now, THAT doctrine has become definite. Definite precisely because it contradicts, and no presumably, no subsequent Pope can possibly adopt the position the Church taught and maintained from her earliest days until the election of Pope Francis.

        Does this strike anyone else as odd? Repeating what the Church has always taught is not at all weighty. Introducing a novelty is infinitely weighty.

        (And no, pointing to the Immaculate Conception and other late definitions will not do, as Pope Pius IX took pains to say that, “this doctrine always existed in the Church as a doctrine that has been received from our ancestors, and that has been stamped with the character of revealed doctrine. For the Church of Christ, watchful guardian that she is, and defender of the dogmas deposited with her, never changes anything, never diminishes anything, never adds anything to them”. That is, he closed a disputed question, but only be resolving *against* novelty and *toward* tradition.)

        • That “doctrine” is nowhere near “definite” because he hasn’t taught it. I.e., he either expresses the keys and claims an extraordinary act or does not. But here the very problem is that what he is addressing is part of the ordinary universal magisterium of the Church. The teaching of 20 centuries of pontiffs isn’t that easily set aside by a pontiff suggesting rewriting a catechism. The canonic authority of the “suggestion” is actually inferior to the canonic authority of the prior teaching. Moreover, there is a difficulty in understanding whether this is even possible: ordinary universal teaching does not appear to be essentially “abrogateable”. Your remark indicates a view of this as though popes were building a new revelation with legos. But there is one revelation, which closed with the death of the last apostle, and what has always and everywhere been taught isn’t revocable. That places limits on the possibility for papal action, which is why it is possible for a pope (e.g., Honorius) to err on a doctrinal matter (as he was condemned for doing, although not as a formal heretic, but still condemned).

          • I think you may have read my comment backwards, or not noticed it was in reply to Prof Fastiggi, not to Prof Trabbic/

            I was basically indicating that Prof Fastiggi’s position led to the absurd consequence that a Pope reaffirming the constant magisterium is an act of little or no magisterial “weight”, while a Pope contradicting the established teaching is given overwhelming weight.

            Doctrine, of course, does not work that way, since it was given once and for all time. We are rightly suspicious of novelties, rather than blithely sweeping away thousands of years of teaching each time the “wind of doctrine” stirs.

      • This conclusion, which is admirably formulated, regarding the need to follow the magisterium rather than any particular doctor, also concerns the need to assent to ordinary universal magisterium. It is extremely difficult to argue that the essential validity of the death penalty for grave crime–not the necessity to impose it in all circumstances, but the essential legitimacy of the penalty for grave crime–is not the ordinary and universal teaching of the magisterium. It seems to fit the conditions both for collegial infallibility and for the infallibility of the ordinary magisterium. This validity has also always been predicated upon the dignity of the imago dei rather than the contrary: both negatively (predation on the creature who carries the imago merits the greatest penalty) and positively (the imago is such that a felon who suffers the penalty with contrition, expiating sin, may thereby find it the gate to paradise), the validity of the penalty has been founded on precisely that which the recent statement says to be what invalidates it. Innumerable catechisms propound this teaching. Is it possible that 20 centuries of pontiffs have taught something to be morally good that is gravely evil? That conclusion is not self-evidently a manner of honoring the Petrine charism and the teaching authority of the pope. Perhaps there is a way to reconcile all this. But it does not immediately present itself, and the obligation of the Catholic is to hold the universal teaching of the magisterium: what obligation can there be, to hold that all prior popes taught that sin was virtuous? It must be kept in mind that the Pope has expressed what he would like to see occur, but this has not occurred, and there are reasons to think that the desideratum is in itself not possible.

  5. That the death penalty is permissible and in some cases even required by civil authorities is part of the human moral law, just as killing in self-defense. To say a Christian must regard these things as inherently wrong is like teaching pacifism as required of all Christians. Pacifism can in some times and places look that way but it is not and cannot in practice be held to by all upright persons at all times. Perhaps that fact doesn’t matter to those disposed to regard moral absolutes as unattainable ideals anyway.

    • The papal Magisterium since John Paul II has restricted the possible use of the death penalty to cases when there is no other possible way of defending human lives against the unjust aggressor (CCC 2267). This is not the same as pacifism. Both John Paul and Pope Francis have affirmed the possible use of military force. They both have also spoken out against the use of capital punishment in today’s world. Their reasons are not merely prudential. This, though, would take too long to explain in this setting.

      • Indeed the magisterium has not taught pacifism, nor could it. But neither then can it teach that the death penalty is not permissible when it is not the case that “bloodless do not suffice.” Agreed, for a Catholic, to be in favor of it, and to be in favor of it only when bloodless means do not suffice, are the same. But do bloodless means suffice? There, reasonable persons can disagree.

        Let’s also agree that there is no “logical space” for further elaboration (I won’t abuse the term and say “development”) beyond “permissible (and sometimes even obligatory) when bloodless means do not suffice.”

  6. The question is – waht is meant by “thomistic”? Is it the method or the result?

    And is “thomistic” always right? I guess not.

    I argue you can reach the teaching of the Immaculate conception “thomistically” while St. Thomas himself was wrong on that issue.

    “Thomistic” can be attributed to the method (and presuppositions!) of Thomas (the method alone would be scholastic) while sometimes reaching different opinions than St. Thomas himself. I am pretty confident he himself would agree.

  7. Nonsense.
    Such scholarly adroitness spun ad nauseam to convolute a non-issue.
    Instead, look at what Jesus did and did not say.
    Luke Chapter 23, 39-43.
    Now one of the criminals hanging there reviled Jesus, saying, “Are you not the Messiah? Save yourself and us.”
    The other, however, rebuking him, said in reply, “Have you no fear of God, for you are subject to the same condemnation?
    And indeed, we have been condemned justly, for the sentence we received corresponds to our crimes, but this man has done nothing criminal.”
    Then he said, “Jesus, remember me when you come into your kingdom.”
    He replied to him, “Amen, I say to you, today you will be with me in Paradise.”

    Look closely at what the “Good” thief said:
    1. “We are under the same condemnation” – i.e., death
    2. “We have been condemned justly.”
    3. “The sentence we received corresponds to our crimes.”

    Now, pay close attention to what Jesus says in response – NOTHING!
    Our Lord did not correct or abjure a single syllable of the Good Thief’s discourse in rebuking his condemned associate.
    This is THE sound Theological, Scriptural, Traditional basis for the death penalty.

2 Trackbacks / Pingbacks

  1. Is opposition to the death penalty Thomistic? -
  2. Capital punishment: Intrinsically evil or morally permissible? – Catholic World Report

Leave a Reply to Michael Pakaluk Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published.

All comments posted at Catholic World Report are moderated. While vigorous debate is welcome and encouraged, please note that in the interest of maintaining a civilized and helpful level of discussion, comments containing obscene language or personal attacks—or those that are deemed by the editors to be needlessly combative or inflammatory—will not be published. Thank you.


*